Tuesday, 19 February 2008

book review end of faith by sam harris



Book Review: The End of Faith, by Sam Harris

Note: I have issued a partial retraction to this review.

A Book with Broad Media Exposure

Some time ago, I returned from work one evening and, as I often do,

tuned in to Fox News. That particular evening, I saw something at once

slightly comical, a little surreal, and very important. Sam Harris, a

man who, to my eye anyway, resembles the comedic actor Ben Stiller,

was being interviewed about a book called The End of Faith: Religion,

Terror, and the Future of Reason . I remember very little about the

interview itself now. What I do recall is my utter astonishment at the

sorts of fundamental questions Harris was raising about religion on

national television, and on a conservative network to boot. I was

astounded. This book had the potential to either very good or very

bad. Regardless, because the book clearly sought to examine the role

of religion in fomenting terrorism, it certainly had the potential to

be, for good or ill, a very important book. Furthermore, the fact that

Fox News was interviewing its author indicated that the book would

likely not remain obscure for long. (Indeed, the author has had other

national exposure.) Based on these things, as well as the fact that

Harris made some excellent points in his interview, I decided to read

the book and see for myself.

A Mixed Bag Worth Rummaging Through

In my experience with books like this that attempt to tackle major

issues, I have usually been either extremely pleased or displeased,

and this evaluation has lasted from cover to cover. This book was an

interesting exception. Harris did deliver on his promise to ask hard

questions about religion, but the book never really got off the

ground. Having said that, the book was not a serious disappointment,

either. As I stated some time ago, one of my greatest concerns about

the book is that it would "champion some new version of revealed truth

as a means of knowledge. [The book] would then end up aiding religion

while appearing to champion reason." While the book did advocate

certain methods from Eastern mysticism, it did so in an unpersuasive

and muddled way. Thus my greatest fear went substantially unrealized.

How could this be? How does one start out coldly examining the tenets

and history of Judaism, Christianity, and Islam, but end up espousing

a woozy mixture of reason, "empirical" exploration, altruism, and

Eastern spirituality? One clue that quickly becomes apparent to many

readers, is that the book is somewhat rambling and poorly organized.

For example, I can summarize the main point of his book in one

sentence as follows: "Since man acts upon the philosophical principles

he holds (sometimes with fatal consequences to himself and others), we

can not afford to withhold our moral judgment from those who accept

such guidance on faith." But I never got this in any one place in the

book. Instead, the reader will find the two halves of this stated

repeatedly in various parts of the book, especially in the first

chapter, where Harris seems to be trying to make his main point. For

example: (1) "A belief is a lever that, once pulled, moves almost

everything else in a person's life." (p. 12), and (2) "It is

imperative that we begin speaking plainly about the absurdity of most

of our religious beliefs" (p. 48).

This lack of focus is a symptom of a broader problem that causes the

book as a whole to suffer: Harris does not appear to possess a

systematic philosophy. My general impression is that Harris is an

implicitly rational man grappling with the major problem (a hostile

Moslem army of medieval savages with access to modern weapons) of his

age, but that he is also, unfortunately, too much a product of his

times. As such, he is also explicitly an altruist and has absorbed

many of the philosophical premises one might expect from someone who

hails from the Academy of our day. The book ends up being something

like a roller-coaster going nowhere. One moment, Harris seems on the

verge of making a major insight. But he does not, to the frustration

of the reader. The next, he seems about to make some monstrous

concession to nihilism or religion. Again, he does not, to the

reader's relief. Overall, the book has little new, philosophically, to

offer its readers. However, it remains an important book for several

reasons. First, the book brings some important questions about the

epistemology of religion to the public discourse. Second, the book

provides a frank look at religious tenets from several Western

traditions throughout history. Given the widespread ignorance about

religion in our own modern culture, even (or especially) on the part

of the religious, it is crucial that the public become familiar with

the full extent of the barbarity contained in religious texts. Third,

the book examines the historical consequences of religious beliefs

being widely and fervently enough held that they can be put into

practice. Fourth, the philosophical deficiencies of the book are

undercut by its main thesis. As such, it is worth knowing what they

are. In this way, the better-informed intellectuals from my readership

will know whether they might wish to address these issues themselves.

I will discuss each of these points in turn for most of the rest of

this review.

Faith as a Means of Knowledge

Though I intend to discuss some of the philosophical deficiencies of

this book in more detail later, it is impossible to begin discussing

this book in any meaningful way without touching upon the hierarchical

nature of philosophic concepts. This book is clearly intended to be an

indictment of beliefs accepted on faith. But faith is an

epistemological concept. That is, it is one way of answering the

question, "How do we know what we know?" A grave weakness of this book

is that it neither summarizes nor points its reader to an adequate

defense of reason as a means of gaining valid knowledge. Rather, the

book seems to either assume that the reader agrees with the validity

of reason, that no such validation is necessary, or worst, that no

such validation is possible. As a result, the book is vulnerable to

the charge that its author is asking us to accept -- on faith -- the

validity of reason! As I have already said, the book is quite sloppy

philosophically, and as a consequence, the book is permeated with

undefended assumptions, which I will have to point out from time to

time.

Assuming the validity of reason as a means of acquiring knowledge, as

most of the American adults in the target audience more or less would,

the first chapter makes many interesting and mostly valuable points,

though there are also grave errors. First, Harris echoes the lifelong

message of Ayn Rand in illustrating the truth of the proposition that

ideas are important: men base their actions on what they hold to be

true. Given the propensity of our media to attribute the atrocities of

September 11, 2001 to almost anything but the beliefs of the

terrorists (or even in the case of Reuters, to pass moral judgment on

them), it is crucial to reestablish this connection. This is indeed

the most important point of this book. If the book achieves nothing

else, it will have done a great service in making people cognizant of

the importance of ideas as movers of history. Harris makes some other

valid and interesting, though derivative, points. His discussion of

religious "moderation" in a section of the first chapter will be a

challenge to any moderately religious reader and a clarion call for

the rest. His basic question for religious moderates is: "How do you

know what to keep and what to discard?"

[W]e must decide what it means to be a religious "moderate" in the

twenty-first century. Moderates in every faith are obliged to loosely

interpret (or simply ignore) much of their canons in the interests of

living in the modern world. ... [T]he moderate's retreat from

scriptural literalism ... draws its inspiration not from scripture but

from cultural developments that have rendered many of God's utterances

difficult to accept as written. In America, religious moderation is

further enforced by the fact that most Christians and Jews do not read

the Bible in its entirety and consequently have no idea just how

vigorously ... God ... wants heresy expunged. (pp. 17-18)

Harris then quotes a Biblical passage (Deuteronomy 13:7-11) that

explicitly calls for believers to slay anyone who would "... divert

you from Yahweh your God...." He further rightly points out that

religious moderation "offers no bulwark against religious extremism"

(p.20) because religious moderates "betray faith and reason equally"

(p.21). He points out that religious knowledge, unlike fields of

rational inquiry, admits of no progress. (This is interesting and

true, but again, not a valid philosophical argument against the

epistemology of faith.) On one point, that religious dogmas about

death and the afterlife are essential to the influence of religious

belief, Harris makes what sounds on its face like a good argument, but

which is not. He ends by saying that, "Without death, the influence of

faith-based religion would be unthinkable." While it is certainly true

that, say, the perpetrators of the September 11 atrocities in New York

and Washington believed that they'd be going to paradise, is it really

necessary for an ethical system to posit an afterlife to cause men to

act irrationally? What of the Communists and the Nazis? Communism and

socialism, while not traditional religions, provide counterexamples of

secular religions which led to barbarism and death, but which did not

offer "pie in the sky when you die" to their adherents. (Harris

discusses the Holocaust later on in the book, but does not address

this issue.) Harris then goes on to make the first of several calls

for something he alternately calls "mysticism" and "spirituality."

[T]here is little doubt that a certain range of human experience can

be appropriately described as "spiritual" or "mystical" -- experiences

of meaningfulness, selflessness, and heightened emotion that surpass

our narrow identities as "selves" [emphasis added] and escape our

current understanding of the mind and brain. But nothing about these

experiences justifies arrogant and exclusionary claims about the

unique sanctity of any text. There is no reason that our ability to

sustain ourselves emotionally and spiritually cannot evolve with

technology, politics, and the rest of culture. (pp. 39-40)

Thus Harris ends a chapter that begins with a probing and

uncompromising examination of faith with a non sequitur about the

importance of fear of death and a call for "mysticism" that, we will

see, he doesn't ask us to examine too closely.

Kant Lite

I do not know much about Eastern mysticism. However, I suspect that

Harris's non sequitur about the importance of fear of death and his

characterization of mystical experiences above and elsewhere as

"selfless" (or unified with the universe) are his way of addressing

the "problem" posed by death: deny that you're really an individual.

This is made easy to do when the essential question of "What is man?"

is glossed over. A strict, hierarchical approach to philosophic

questions however, would require that we determine what we are before

determining what we should do. In other words, how the hell does

Harris know that we are not individuals? (As he asserts by using scare

quotes around the word "selves" above.) No answer. How does he know

these experiences provide valid knowledge? He mentions that science is

beginning to investigate the kinds of experiences he is alluding to,

but science is derived from a specific philosophical perspective on

the world and how knowledge is acquired. Any gains from these studies

will merely add to already validated scientific knowledge about our

minds. And how do we even begin to "sustain ourselves emotionally"

without a firm grasp of what an emotion is? If Ayn Rand is correct, an

emotion is a nearly instantaneous evaluation of one's surroundings

based on one's value system which is felt as a percept. If this is

true, an emotion -- "heightened" or otherwise -- tells one nothing

about himself without some degree of self-knowledge or introspection.

But I belabor the point. And, besides, the epistemological meltdown

has just begun.

In one sense, Harris does exactly what I feared he might in that he

does, in fact, attempt to sell his readers on the notion of some

nonrational means of knowledge. He does even more than this, though.

He essentially discounts the validity of reason. Harris echoes an

argument posed by Immanuel Kant by dressing it in pseudoscientifc

garb. As Ayn Rand formulated the argument in For the New Intellectual:

[Kant's] argument amounted to a negation, not only of man's

consciousness, but of any consciousness, of consciousness as such. His

argument, in essence, ran as follows: man is limited to a

consciousness of a specific nature, which perceives by specific means

and no others, therefore, his consciousness is not valid; man is

blind, because he has eyes -- deaf, because he has ears -- deluded,

because he has a mind -- and the things he perceives do not exist,

because he perceives them. (p. 30)

So how does Harris (who is, like myself, a neurobiologist) make this

argument sound scientific? How, that is, does he appeal to our minds

to make them believe that they are not really grasping reality?

The claims of mystics are neurologically quite astute. No human being

has ever experienced an objective world, or even a world at all. You

are, at the moment, having a visionary experience. The world that you

see and hear is nothing more than a modification of your

consciousness, the physical status of which remains a mystery. Your

nervous system sections the undifferentiated buzz of the universe into

separate channels of sight, sound, taste, and touch, as well as other

senses of lesser renown -- proprioception, kinesthesia,

enteroreception, and even echolocation. The sights and sounds and

pulsings that you experience at this moment are like different spectra

of light thrown forth by the prism of your brain. We really are such

stuff as dreams are made of. ... [N]othing arises in consciousness

that has not first been structured, edited, or amplified by the

nervous system. ... [T]his gives rise to a few philosophical problems

concerning the foundations of our knowledge.... (p. 41)

How does Sam Harris know with such certainty that "no human being has

ever experienced an objective world?" No answer. I do not intend to

present Ayn Rand's full theory of epistemology here to rebut Sam

Harris. Besides, she and her student Leonard Peikoff have already done

a much better job of that than I ever could. At this point, I think it

sufficient simply to state that as a scientist who understands

Harris's gratuitous jargon perfectly well, that he is either trying to

pull the wool over our eyes or actually believes that our grasp of the

world is shaky at best. I suspect the latter. Harris is so

disorganized philosophically, and his views so commonplace, that it

would be easy to attribute nearly the whole of his set of beliefs to

his having picked them up fairly uncritically from others. (Though his

extensive notes and bibliography might make that tough to defend.)

Furthermore, though Harris presents this Kantesque formulation and

continues advocating "mysticism" later in the book, he succeeds in

doing very little damage in doing so. First, these are notions with

such common currency, that they will likely have been accepted or

rejected already by any educated reader. Second, Harris fails to make

a very convincing case against the validity of the mind or for

adopting Eastern mysticism. (In fact, it's hard to see what, exactly,

we are to accomplish via the latter in any case.) Finally, the central

points of the book -- that ideas are important and thus should not be

accepted on faith -- serve to undercut the very bad ideas Harris holds

and wants us to adopt! Not to exaggerate the importance of this book,

but so it was with Aristotle: though he made many errors, his rational

methodology enabled later generations to recover from them. This is

why, though I have objected lengthily already to some of the ideas in

Harris's book, I still regard it as beneficial in the main.

Taking Altruism on Faith OK?

The second chapter consists of Harris's ruminations on "the nature of

belief." It is here that he develops further his idea that belief is a

guide to action. More importantly, he marshals his arguments against

accepting beliefs based on faith. He makes several damning indictments

of faith that will appeal to most readers who respect reason. This

chapter, infuriatingly, almost ends strongly. I would have liked it to

end on this quote.

What about our much championed freedom of religious belief? It is no

different from our freedoms of journalistic and biological belief --

and anyone who believes that the media are perpetrating a great fire

conspiracy, or that molecular biology is just a theory that may prove

totally wrong, has merely exercised his freedom to be thought a fool.

Religious unreason should acquire an even greater stigma in our

discourse, given that it remains among the principle causes of armed

conflict in the world. Before you can get to the end of this

paragraph, another person will probably die because of what someone

else believes about God. Perhaps it is time we demanded that our

fellow human beings had better reasons for maintaining their religious

differences, if such reasons even exist. (pp. 77-78)

Unfortunately, just as Harris ends the first chapter with a major

epistemological error, he ends this one with an ethical one, by

praising altruism. "But there are far better reasons for

self-sacrifice than those that religion provides" (p. 78). As Harris

has spent the whole chapter discussing belief, one can't help but

wonder, "How does Harris 'know' that there is even a single 'good'

reason to commit self-sacrifice?" He does not. We have here yet

another example of a common belief -- that morality equals

self-sacrifice -- that Harris has accepted, but failed to address pro

or con, or apparently, even to think about at all. Nonetheless, the

larger point of this chapter makes reading it worthwhile.

The Historical Consequences of Faith

Much of the rest of the book does a great service to mankind by

cataloging some of the more ridiculous things people have believed on

faith and the consequences that have been felt through history

whenever faith has had the upper hand in society. Although the book

takes Islamofascist terrorism as its point of departure, Christianity

and Judaism are not spared its critical eye. This is important in that

a focus on Islam alone would too easily allow the Christians in our

country to see our modern crisis incorrectly as a sectarian conflict

rather than as a direct consequence of the divorce from reason that is

religion as such. Furthermore, it is important that our Christians,

believing in a highly attenuated version of Christianity and without

anything like medieval (or Moslem) fervency, grasp the essence of what

they really are advocating. In this respect, Sam Harris does an

admirable job of preventing Christians from evading what their

professed beliefs would really mean when put into practice. As I have

stated earlier, Harris seems to be implicitly rational. I will add

that he errs on the side of empiricism, but that in this case, it is a

felicitous error. The many and detailed examples here help drive the

point home. Harris successively describes in detail the following

Christian horrors: the Inquisition, the persecution of witches and

Jews, and the complicity of the Roman Catholic Church in the

Holocaust. He then devotes a half a chapter to the medieval nature of

modern-day Islam. The barbarity listed here is so extensive it

sometimes becomes tedious. Some highlights: numerous exhortations to

Moslem men to "defend" the faith via armed conflict; a list (by place

and year) of 51 massacres of Jews within the Arab world; five pages of

quotations from the Koran (in order of appearance) where unbelievers

are vilified; and polling data from all over the Moslem world

indicating that, at least, 20% (in relatively secular Turkey) of the

general public in any given Moslem nation say that suicide bombing in

"defense" of Islam is justifiable. After this chapter, he devotes a

chapter to the less-than-benign influence of Christianity on

modern-day America. Harris provides a few illuminating quotes from

government officials, discusses the exorbitant cost of enforcing drug

laws, and touches on the threat posed by Christians to embryonic stem

cell research.

But if Harris does a good job showing the ramifications of religious

belief put into practice, he does a poor one suggesting how to dodge

the scimitar it wields today. As he has implicitly rational, but

explicitly mixed epistemological premises, he likewise implicitly

favors survival, but explicitly gives the moral high ground to

pacifists, consistent with someone who seems to have absorbed many of

his ideas from the dominant intellectual culture.

What will we do if an Islamist regime ... ever acquires long-range

nuclear weaponry? ... In such a situation, the only thing likely to

ensure our survival may be a nuclear first strike of our own. Needless

to say, this would be an unthinkable crime [emphasis added]-- as it

would kill tens of millions of innocent civilians in a single day --

but it may be the only course of action available to us, given what

the Islamists believe. (p. 129)

If it isn't a crime to kill, in self-defense, an individual pointing a

gun at you, neither is it be a crime for us to launch a first strike

in the situation described above. Every death would lie on the

shoulders of the Islamists and those who armed them. But Harris is so

crippled by altruism that he can scarcely rise to the defense of his

own life! In fact, Harris's altruism permeates the second half of the

chapter called "The Problem with Islam" (where he lists the many

barbarities of Islam as indicated above). As a result he ends up

wasting considerable time manufacturing a convoluted argument (the

"perfect weapon") for America's self-defense after first conceding

every major premise (and then some) to, of all people, Noam Chomsky!

This is a man who has worked tirelessly for decades to tar the United

States as a global villain. How does Harris describe Chomsky? "He

appears to be an exquisitely moral man whose political views prevent

him from making the most basic moral distinctions -- between types of

violence, and the variety of human purposes that give rise to them"

(139). For a through debunking of Chomsky's political views and

academic reputation, refer to The Anti-Chomsky Reader , edited by

Peter Collier and David Horowitz. Suffice it to say, that some of the

worst damage Sam Harris's book could possibly inflict on our national

discourse about the war would be through setting up a figure such as

Chomsky as a moral authority. Again, though, most educated readers

already have formed an opinion on Chomsky or will at least have

already encountered the substance of his ravings in comic-book form

through their familiarity with Michael Moore.

Harris continues his infuriating ethical hobble in the penultimate

chapter, "A Science of Good and Evil." As he does in much of the book,

he makes a succession of good and bad points in no particular order.

Fortunately, he makes his best point immediately at the start of the

chapter. In fact, it is such a fundamentally good point that it

salvages the remainder of the chapter by inviting criticism. To wit:

Many people appear to believe that ethical truths are culturally

contingent in a way that scientific truths are not. Indeed this loss

of purchase on ethical truth seems to be one of the principle

shortcomings of secularism. The problem is that once we abandon our

belief in a rule-making God, the question of why a given action is

good or bad becomes a matter of debate. And a statement like "Murder

is wrong," while being uncontroversial in most circles, has never

seemed anchored to the facts of this world in the way that statements

about planets or molecule appear to be. The problem, in philosophical

terms, has been one of characterizing just what sorts of "facts" our

moral intuitions can be said to track -- if, indeed, they track

anything of the kind. (p. 170)

His basic point is that ethics can be approached with reference to the

facts of reality. Never mind that he earlier calls into question the

ability of the human mind to grasp objective reality. Never mind that

he spends a lot of time trying, in turn, to base ethics on the

"happiness and suffering of sentient creatures," or on "intuition," or

on "moral communities" -- in short, on anything but what we are and

what we must do to survive. If we consider the latter two things and

approach questions of morality with the proper methodology, we will

reach the correct answers. As with the rest of the book, Harris

presents an idea whose time has come, but goes nowhere in particular

with it. Though Harris develops further ethical arguments in this

chapter, it will suffice to say that they are convoluted, somewhat

tedious, and for the most part, easily avoidable through a more

systematic approach to philosophy. In addition to being an altruist,

Harris, incidentally, is also a determinist. Since this position, his

assertion to the contrary, directly contradicts the notion of ethical

accountability, I will present here the counterargument to determinism

as articulated by Leonard Peikoff in Objectivism: The Philosophy of

Ayn Rand.

If man's consciousness were automatic, if it did react

deterministically to outer or inner forces acting upon it, then, by

definition, a man would have no choice in regard to his mental

content; he would accept whatever he had to accept, whatever ideas the

determining forces engendered in him. In such a case, one could not

prescribe methods to guide a man's thought or ask him to justify his

ideas; the subject of epistemology would be inapplicable. One cannot

ask a person to alter or justify the mentally inescapable, any more

than, in physical terms, one can ask him to alter or justify his

pattelar reflex. In regard to the involuntary, there is no alternative

but to submit -- to do what one must, whatever that is. (pp. 69-70)

Free will is a philosophic axiom, and as such, any attempt to argue

against it will result in self-contradiction. In this case, the

determinist, as such, would essentially be squawking like a parrot.

Having no choice as to the content of his mind, he will be unable to

evaluate it. According to his own position, he will be unable to know

whether what he is saying -- like an argument in favor of determinism

-- is true or false.

Billions and Billions of "Selves"

We finally reach the last chapter, where Sam Harris revisits the idea

of "mysticism," a term which he strangely chooses over "spirituality"

because he somehow regards it as having -- I am not making this up --

more "gravitas." Thus culminates in stupidity a book that began on

such a promising note. I risk sounding overly harsh to a man who has

done us all a great service by asking some very important questions

and by bringing up some very important historical facts. Nevertheless,

I have a point. I think that Harris means well by offering the

meditative techniques of Eastern mysticism to us as a method of

attaining enlightenment and of spiritual sustenance. However, I not

only have numerous major issues with many of the other points he has

already raised in this book, I take issue with this suggestion as

well. As do hallucinogenic drugs, meditation may indeed offer, under a

carefully controlled program of scientific study, some insights on how

the mind works. It also undoubtedly provides many with a way to relax.

But the suggestion that we are not, in fact, separate entities, based

on some out-of-context scientific facts and on certain states achieved

during meditation, is ludicrous. It is also precisely the kind of

absurd result that can -- and almost always will -- be achieved when

philosophy is approached in an unfocused, undisciplined manner. One of

the subheadings for this chapter sums up the problem nicely: "What are

we calling 'I'?" Throughout much of this book, Harris has built

ethical arguments. These are arguments concerning how human beings

should act. Should we not be clear on the question of what, exactly, a

human being is before we start telling him what to do? (And should he

listen to us if we give him orders or lousy arguments?) At the risk of

sounding like a broken record, Eastern mysticism is not an idea that

is either especially new to most readers or compellingly-enough

presented for the book to become a significant source for the spread

of bad ideas. For this reason, the final chapter will probably seem to

most readers like an interesting, Carl Saganesque bit of wonderment

about the amazing universe we all reside in, and nothing more.

Conclusion

The End of Faith is an important book whose lack of philosophical

focus hinders itself from greatness. The principle virtues of the book

are twofold. First, the book brings to the general public discourse

the following four propositions. (1) That ideas guide man's actions,

which can include unprovoked mass murder. (2) That faith as a means of

gaining knowledge is invalid. (3) That we can therefore no longer

afford to withhold moral condemnation of those who indulge in faith.

(4) Furthermore, areas of knowledge once regarded as within the

provenance of faith can and should be discussed just as rationally as

any science. Second, the book details what life "guided" by faith

really is like by examining the history of the West as well as the

current situation in the Moslem world. By posing the questions he does

in the relevant context, Sam Harris succeeds in shifting the debate

about what we should do about Islamofascism to a more fundamental

question: "Can we afford to suffer the faithful in silence?"

Unfortunately, Sam Harris, though he seems well-intentioned and

implicitly rational, he approaches philosophical issues in an

undisciplined manner that is, at times, explicitly anti-reason and

altruistic. This poor methodology manifests itself in a variety of

ways: the poor organization of the book, a sometimes plodding prose,

numerous instances of missed opportunities to improve upon good

points, and numerous trips down philosophical blind alleys that are,

alas, already too well-traveled in this day and age. The fact that the

book reaches these conclusions is, fortunately, far outweighed by the

book's more fundamental message, which I think deserves to be

formulated as Thomas Jefferson once put it, "Fix reason firmly in her

seat, and call to her tribunal every fact, every opinion. Question

with boldness even the existence of God.... Read the Bible, then, as

you would read Livy or Tacitus." To the extent that he has succeeded

in reminding us forcefully of such great sentiments, Sam Harris

deserves our thanks.

Note: I have issued a partial retraction to this review.

-- CAV

Updates:

1-3-05: Corrected typo in one quote. Corrected one link. Included link

to partial retraction at beginning and end. Added links to

Introduction to Objectivist Epistemology and Objectivism: The

Philosphy of Ayn Rand.

11-9-06: Added links to Amazon for all books.

Posted at 1:59 AM. Permalink

Share this story.

blogmarks [spc.png] del.icio.us [spc.png] digg [spc.png] Furl

[spc.png] NewsVine [spc.png] RawSugar [spc.png] Reddit [spc.png] Simpy

[spc.png] TailRank [spc.png] YahooMyWeb [spc.png] Stumble it

10 Comments:

Gus,

You did a yoeman's job dissecting End of Faith, finding its strengths

and weaknesses. But what I find most interesting about Harris's very

provocative but disorganized and over-stuffed book is that it has

created such a stir, a stir which continues from hard cover into soft

cover, almost two years since its original publication. It is striking

a chord, a nerve,an anxiety. If there was no Sam Harris, he'd have to

be invented. Perhaps endless struggles with Middle East forces

accounts for some of it. But I suspect that the fundamentalist

movement in this country may have as much or,increasingly, more to do

with it. Theocratic tyranny is frightening to many Americans, whatever

its geographic or theological headwater.

Stuart

Posted by Anonymous stuart on February 12, 2006 6:28 PM

Stuart,

Thanks, and I'm glad you found this useful. I would agree that the

interest in the book is also fed by fear of our own theocrats in

America. This makes Harris's book doubly shameful.

Gus

Posted by Blogger Gus Van Horn on February 12, 2006 9:18 PM

As Ayn Rand formulated the argument in For the New Intellectual:

[Kant's] argument amounted to a negation, not only of man's

consciousness, but of any consciousness, of consciousness as such. His

argument, in essence, ran as follows: man is limited to a

consciousness of a specific nature, which perceives by specific means

and no others, therefore, his consciousness is not valid; man is

blind, because he has eyes -- deaf, because he has ears -- deluded,

because he has a mind -- and the things he perceives do not exist,

because he perceives them. (p. 30)

So how does Harris (who is, like myself, a neurobiologist) make this

argument sound scientific? How, that is, does he appeal to our minds

to make them believe that they are not really grasping reality?

[...]

How does Sam Harris know with such certainty that "no human being has

ever experienced an objective world?" No answer. I do not intend to

present Ayn Rand's full theory of epistemology here to rebut Sam

Harris.

I have only just begun to read the Harris book (and am already having

serioud probems with the disinenguous treatment of Chomsky I came

across [discussion here from Harris's own webpage]).But your remarks

on Kant caught my attention. One may well disagree with Kant (it's

easy), but one should disagree with what he actually said. Your

treatment of Kant seems to imply that he posits a universal

subjectivism; this could not be further from the case. The structures

of intuition and the categories are (he believes, at least) the very

basis for receiving objective content about the world. He does not say

that we do not perceive reality; he says that we do have knowledge of

the objectively true world. Wanting to know more than science can

provide (what science provides is precisely knowledge of this

objective world), that is, wanting a "god's-eye" view of the world,

that is what Kant claims we can't have. I seriously doubt that

objectivists believe that we can know everything that has ever

happened or that will ever happen--that would be exactly what this

god's-eye view would provide, and which Kant claims we can't have.

One may disagree with Kant, either because one believes that objective

knowledge is impossible, or because one believes that objective

knowledge is obtained in some other way, but to ascribe this kind of

subjectivism to Kant is really to not understood his position.

Kant does sometimes use the word "reality" [Wirklichkeit] at times to

refer to this "god's-eye view" world, but, again, I doubt that Ayn

Rand is claiming that humans have that kind of knowledge (otherwise

the objection would rest on equivocation involving "reality"). (See

the Critique of Judgment, remark to section 76. German)

OK, maybe I'm being nitpicky. But one should disagree with him for

what he actually believed.

Posted by Anonymous blog responder on February 19, 2006 5:03 PM

B.R.,

You say,

[Kant] does not say that we do not perceive reality; he says that we

do have knowledge of the objectively true world. Wanting to know more

than science can provide (what science provides is precisely knowledge

of this objective world), that is, wanting a "god's-eye" view of the

world, that is what Kant claims we can't have. I seriously doubt that

objectivists believe that we can know everything that has ever

happened or that will ever happen--that would be exactly what this

god's-eye view would provide, and which Kant claims we can't have.

You could help me understand what you are trying to say by explaining

the difference between "perceiving reality" and "having knowledge of

the objectively true world" by means of perception. Your argument

makes it sound like Kant thinks that to know anything, we must be

omniscient.

Rand certainly does not claim that we are omniscient, nor is it

necessary to have to know everything about reality to know something

about it with certainty.

If Kant hold that we can "perceive reality[ without having] knowledge

of the objectively true world", then he is claiming that we don't

grasp reality through our senses.

Gus

Posted by Blogger Gus Van Horn on February 21, 2006 12:17 PM

Dear Gus,

I'm so interested to have a copy of Sam Harris End of Faith.

Unfortunately, I live in the most believer country in religion of

Islam Saudi Arabia. They will not allow this book for Saudis to read

and ordering a hard copy will get me in trouble with local

authorities. I'm not sure how you can help me getting a full PDF copy.

By the way, there is a considerable number of atheists in Saudi. We

cannot reveal ourselves as atheist and lack of freedom to read makes

non-believers to minimum. Thanks to internet that allows us read some

exerts of the opposite opinion. Believing in Islam in Saudi Arabia is

a must not a choice. I wonder how someone chooses to believe when he

or she have no choice to not believe.

If by any means you or your readers can send me a PDF copy of the book

please send it to: perfume_my_life@hotmail.com

Salim

Thanks

Posted by Anonymous Anonymous on May 24, 2006 4:36 AM

Thanks for this review. It is a fairly accurate summary of my thoughts

on the book, but I could not have expressed them as well. Plus I'm too

lazy to go to all that work. ;-)

I've recommended the book to all my friends despite its flaws. I think

it is a good book that could have been great, but the ideas in it are

ideas that need to be discussed, pondered, dissected, and argued

about. By everyone -- agree or disagree with them, the subjects Harris

opines on are subjects everyone needs talk about.

-- Deryk

Posted by Anonymous Anonymous on September 12, 2006 2:42 PM

Deryk,

Thank you, but I think you're letting Harris off too easily.

A far better book than Harris's would be Ayn Rand's Philosophy: Who

Needs It. Chapter 7 of that book alone is all that needs to be said --

And it has been said better. -- on the subjects Harris talks about.

All the best.

Gus

Posted by Blogger Gus Van Horn on September 12, 2006 3:26 PM

Gus,

I've just given a preliminary skim of your review which I will follow

up with a careful read when I get a chance. It looks like I am in much

the same place you were. I'll let you know what the virdict is upon

further reflection.

Tom

Posted by Blogger Tom Rowland on March 18, 2007 11:59 AM

I would like to comment on two things in this very long review:

"Harris does not appear to possess a systematic philosophy. "

"as a scientist who understands Harris's gratuitous jargon perfectly

well, that he is either trying to pull the wool over our eyes or

actually believes that our grasp of the world is shaky at best."

Regarding the first item there is always the economical question

whether a person should really "start with the big bang" every time he

tries to explain something? My point of view is that Harris' book

wouldn't have become the success it is if one had to wade through a

very long-winded "systematic philosophy". I think his decision to

simply stand on the shoulders of others and assume a little knowledge

in advance by his readers was acceptable.

Also, a very long and very academic rendition of "the great

philosophical issues that be" would have obscured the very poignant

message from Harris (and Dawkins for that matter) that while we debate

the finer points of theology there are VERY practical things happening

right here in very un-philosophical space: planes flying into

buildings, wars being fought and horrible atrocities being committed

by the people of faith. I suppose the Wittgenstein quote got lost

somewhere, but I have to agree that when it comes to suffering we

"just know it's bad". Somehow we hit solid rock. Most humans have the

same basic propensities across cultures when you manage to pull out

the religious factor. (Was it Harris og Dawkins that explained this

best?)

As for the last quote I mention, that is a classic fallacy of

bifurcation. I offer a third explanation: Harris is simply observing

that science has known for a very long time: that we do not so much

"see objective reality" as we "construct a perception that is USEFUL

for us in this Middle World" (the latter phrase is borrowed from

Dawkins and anyone should look up the video "Richard Dawkins on the

strangeness of science: tedtalks" on YouTube).

Posted by Blogger Vad on September 04, 2007 4:28 AM

(1) One needn't explain his entire philosophy in order to have a

systematic philosophy or to argue with one as his basis.

(2) Anyone who claims that you can "know" that you do not "see

objective reality" is contradicting himself.

Posted by Blogger Gus Van Horn on September 04, 2007 4:16 PM

Post a Comment

Backlinks:

See links to this post


No comments: